number of trials where the chance that a double-six will not happen is even, or 1/2:
Using the splendid ability of algebra to re-jig equations in simpler forms, we multiply both sides by ( a + b ) x and by 2, then divide both sides by b x , and get:
For many years, mathematicians would have been stumped at this point. But de Moivre had the benefit of logarithms, which allow us to manipulate equations to isolate exponents like x from the other elements:
Logarithms ease calculation by considering any large number as a base raised to some power (as a million is also 10 6 ). Instead of trying to multiply large numbers, we can simply add the powers of 10 that represent them, since 10 a X 10 b = 10 a+b . So if x =10 a , then a = log x . De Moivre was using ânaturalâ logarithms, which have as their base not 10, but e , a mysteriously prevalent irrational number whose decimal expansion begins as 2.718281 . . . so 2 is a little less than e , roughly e 0.7 .
Â
Once youâve found the logarithm tables in the back of your old high-school textbook, you would have something good enough for most practical purposes. But de Moivre is not yet done. Instead of a and b , letâs talk about 1 and q , so that we can say the odds against success are q to 1; that makes our basic equation (expressed in odds rather than probabilities):
De Moivre had a general method for dealing with crabbed, knotty expressions like log(1 + 1/q), which involved infinite series: that is, adding together an infinite number of terms, thus:
Er, yes . . . and exactly how is algebra helping us here? The formula looks clear enough, but then so do the instructions âMove this mountain using these tweezers.â De Moivre, however, noticed that, assuming q is big enough, all the terms after the first are so small as to make hardly any difference to the totalâparticularly since they alternately add and remove progressively tinier and tinier amounts. In fact, they are usually so small that we can dispense with them completely, allowing us to be reasonably correct without being exact. So, having done this major surgery, we are left with:
A quick glance above will remind you that log 2 is roughly 0.7. So, having started with a vague and general question, algebra offers us a startlingly specific result: given big enough odds against something, you can gauge how many trials are needed to have an even chance of seeing it happen by multiplying the odds by 0.7. This will apply to anything: roulette, cards, eclipses of the moon. In the case of de Méréâs dice, the odds against rolling a double-six are 35 to 1 (as you know); 35 x 0.7 = 24.5 trials: exactly the answer Pascal got by calculating cases.
Infinite series and logarithms also gave de Moivre the key to understanding Pascalâs Triangleâand, with it, the bell curve. A few pages ago we blithely said that if you wanted to know, say, the chance that a heads will appear in n tosses of a coin, you need only count n rows down the triangle and a across to find the coefficient. Easy enough for five or six trials, but imagine actually doing it for a series of 1,000 trials. Here are the tweezersâthere is the mountain. There are clearly good reasons for asking de Moivre and his algebra to help us.
His attack on the problem took advantage of the two most important aspects of logarithms and infinite series: that logarithms allow you to get the result you need by adding logs rather than multiplying big numbers; and that infinite series can converge. That is (as we saw with the series for 1 + 1/q ), although the summing goes on forever, each new term makes progressively less and less difference to the total, so you can see where the series is heading even if you never quite get there. De Moivre then made one of those shifts of viewpoint that define genius in mathematics. Having teased out his formula for the middle term of the n th row of the triangle into an infinite series, he