number of workers in any given industry. Marxism is too âflatteringâ a doctrine, she wrote, because âit teaches the laborer that all the fault is with someone else, that he is the victim of circumstances, and not even a partner in the creation of his own and his childrenâs misery.â
Still searching for a catechism, whatever her disillusion with Marxist orthodoxyâwhatever her lip service to a new intellectual rigorâshe argued once more for the fundamental relationship of sex and reproduction to the economic organization of society. Birth control would not simply promise fewer children and the potential of a higher standard of living. It was, in her newest phrase, an âentering wedgeâ for educating humanity in matters of long-term health and hygiene, which would totally transform their lives. 19
Most important, Margaret attempted to further refine her argument for the essential compatibility of a progressive vision embracing both social reform and eugenics. Again paraphrasing Ellis, she took issue with conventional opposition to contraception on the part of conservatives worried about the reproduction of the âfitterâ classes. There would be no âcradle-competitionâ between the haves and the have-nots, she insisted, because all women, rich and poor alike, would voluntarily limit their childbearing when presented with the option to do so. The one exceptionâthe one population for whom enforced contraception might be necessaryâwere the physically or mentally incompetent, who could not themselves understand the benefits of smaller families. She declared her support for ânegativeâ eugenics, or the weeding out of this âunfitâ population, though she disdained the idea of promoting fertility, or âpositiveâ eugenics.
The woman whose own autobiography so tellingly advertises the births of her ten siblings âwithout a blotch or a blemishâ thus refused to consider that the handicapped may also be worthy, that the rights of the individual, in any event, must reign supreme in a truly democratic society. Nor did she question the reliability and objectivity of standardized methods of determining mental capacity, which were then just becoming much the rage. She was, of course, not alone in these oversights, nor in her willingness to sacrifice the individual rights of the most defenseless to what was being widely touted as the greater social good. Eugenics, for the moment, remained popular with a wide range of progressive thinkers who simply failed to anticipate that the enforcement of hereditarian reforms was likely to foster the very discrimination by ethnicity, race, and class that they denounced and worked elsewhere to combat. Like Ellis, Margaret was intent that biology be incorporated into social reform as a theoretical matter, but never really came to terms with how to do so in practice.
In The Pivot of Civilization she condemned the class bias of many eugenic writings and claimed that beyond âgrossâ examples of mental deficiency, there is no way of deciding the question of fitness in a democratic society. She maintained instead that birth control is where a true eugenic approach to social change must beginâthat only controlled fertility can bring about the education and economic opportunity for women through which responsible motherhood is achieved. The initiative for individual and racial regeneration must âcome from withinâ¦.â she wrote; âit must be autonomous, self-directive, and not imposed from without.â She argued that the great majority of women, once given the opportunity to control their fertility, would willingly accept the responsibility to do soâthat the fecundity of the uneducated and impoverished most often resulted from a lack of access to reliable contraception, not from poor motivation or self-control. And she maintained this conviction throughout her life.
Indeed,